h/t Matt McManus on Noam Chomsky’s Theory of Human Nature (04/16/20), from which much of this is taken
Descartes famously argued that all our empirical knowledge may be an illusion, so it can never provide a basis for absolute certainty. By contrast, we can be certain that we are thinking (“I think, therefore I am”), and so glean some certainty about the nature of cognition.
Kant goes a step further. True, all empirical knowledge may be an illusion, but there is a universal structure to the human mind by which we all perceive the empirical world in more or less the same way. E.g., all human beings see the world in terms of space and time. And since we see the world in the same way, we can gain knowledge that would be accepted by anyone. However, this doesn’t mean we gain knowledge of the world “in itself.” Our knowledge is only of the world as it appears to those structures of the mind (what Kant calls the “phenomenal world”). The world of actual things may or may not match the phenomena we experience, but we’ll never know.
Chomsky applies this toggle from empiricism to Kant to linguistics. McManus mentions how Chomsky’s linguistic theory (beginning in the late 1950s) pushed against such behaviorists as B. F. Skinner. Skinner and the behaviorists assume, like the old empiricists, that the mind is initially a blank slate, and only learns things like language from the experience of being taught. To Chomsky, this behaviorist/empiricist approach falters if we look at language acquisition. If we accept the blank slate premise, he argued, it leads to the conclusion that if one left a rock, a tomato and a baby with a family in London each of them would be equally likely to learn English, since each of them would experience being exposed to that language. The reason that a baby can pick up a language—even several languages—very quickly is that her mind is a priori capable of learning a human dialect. This language faculty also explains why human languages have many deep similarities. Not only do we largely perceive the world in the same way, as Kant points out, but our language faculty generates universal grammars, and much of Chomsky’s linguistic theory is about unraveling those universal grammars.
As with Kant’s theory, this position implies an upside and a downside. The upside is that human beings are capable of understanding one another, and even translating their various languages between each other. The downside is that we are still operating exclusively in the phenomenal world, as our mutual understanding, including cross-cultural communication, is based on the universal structures of how our minds process the world, not on any direct experience of the world “out there.”
I will go the extra step here and align Chomsky in this way with Freud. (As my loyal readers know, I am always eager to shore up Freud’s place in the history of ideas over and against his pitiful detractors, albeit with an occasional concession to those detractors.) What Chomsky rejects in the field of linguistics, Freud rejects in the field of psychology. The behaviorists shunned Freudian psychoanalysis, shunned talking about the internal structure of the mind as if there were something in there anterior to our experience of the world. As in Chomsky the mind has an a priori structure that facilitates language acquisition, so in Freud the mind has an a priori structure that facilitates similarities in development of the psyche across human populations. Whether you see that structure in terms of primitive drives along with mechanisms that develop to inhibit those drives, or as a gradient structure moving from the conscious mind down deeper and deeper into unconscious layers of motivation, Freud’s psychology and Chomsky’s linguistics both defy the “blank slate” theory by positing some internal structure, something intrinsic about the human mind, what Kant might call subjective universals that shape how humans process the world, irrespective of the range of individual human experiences.
In neither Freud’s case nor Chomsky’s, it seems to me, does this leave us with an either/or dilemma. Chomsky’s theory might well elucidate the universal grammars that provide the a priori capacity for language acquisition without demeaning the contribution of behaviorist methods on the other side. Likewise, behaviorist psychology might well provide a stimulus-response model that works quite well as a mechanical operation for changing behaviors, but I see no reason (other than that academics must endlessly produce us vs them models and show the superiority of their side over the other as a way of securing tenure) that this should preclude psychoanalytic investigations of the internal structures of the mind that might underwrite human possibilities, human creativity, and human pathways of dysfunction more generally.
I think, how we learn, what we think, are all, interrelated, because, we don’t just, observe each other and model after one another’s, behaviors, we also, have the intrinsic motivation to drive us towards learning things, and, using one branch of theory alone, like psychodynamic or behaviorism, or even the humanistic approach on how we think and what we do, and what drives us to act a certain way is just too, simplic.
LikeLiked by 2 people
Yes to intellectual pluralism!
LikeLike
Neither Freud nor Chomsky invented innate behaviors nor biological/genetic perspectives. A larger biological perspective, as well as sociological understanding belies any simple approaches to the great psychological question. But Freud and Chomsky were pretty good!
LikeLiked by 1 person
Good points, Bumba!
LikeLiked by 1 person
We are all curious about how and where communication among us humans had its roots. Of course, we can only theorise, but most likely, it originated in our curiosity, forcing us to investigate the surroundings we found ourselves in. The more we got to know the world, the more we were inspired to put names to our discoveries.
However, as our minds were still lacking the tools for reasoning and without the abilities to explain the unexplainable phenomena of reality, our immediate emotional responses to them, language must have had its roots in those first mystical utterances. There is no doubt that philosophies originated in those words that express humanity’s supernatural beliefs before being formed into rational concepts during the enlightenment of the Hellenistic period.
Consequently, we can claim that languages are analytical tools of communication and, in essence, philosophies.
Philosophy can exist only as the science of values, which are universally valid.
Philosophy has its own field and its own problems in these values of universal validity, which are the organising principles for all the functions of culture and civilisation and for all the particular values of life.
LikeLiked by 1 person
Good food for thought, Michael. I imagine control of fire helped too — sitting around the campfire every night , gazing at the flames and the stars and each other — must have made us want to refine our grunts into something more specific 🙂
LikeLiked by 1 person